WHITEHEAD, Alfred North

The Aims of Education and Other Essays

MacMillan, New York 1929 (this edition 1959)

This book contains ten addresses or papers delivered or written by A.N. Whitehead at different times between 1912 and 1928. The general theme is "education on its intellectual side." The topics dealt with are:

I The Aims of Education (24 pp.)

II The Rhythm of Education (20 pp.)

III The Rhythmic Claims of Freedom and Discipline (20 pp.)

IV Technical Education and Its Relation to Science and Literature (28 pp.)

V The Place of Classics in Education (22 pp.)

VI The Mathematical Curriculum (19 pp.)

VII Universities and Their Function (16 pp.)

VIII The Organisation of Thought (26 pp.)

IX The Anatomy of Some Scientific Ideas (51 pp.)

X Space, Time and Relativity (15 pp.)

Only the first seven essays are reviewed here, since they are the only ones directly related to education.

One main idea runs throughout the volume: "The students are alive, and the purpose of education is to stimulate and guide that self-development." The corollary of this idea is that "teachers also should be alive with living thoughts." In short, the whole book is a protest against dead knowledge, that is to say, against inert ideas." (Preface, p. v)

Summary of the First Seven Essays

I. The Aims of Education

Whitehead begins with a definition of culture: "Culture is activity of thought, and receptiveness to beauty and human feelings." (p. 1) On the basis of this somewhat vague and idealistic conception of culture, Whitehead proceeds to his first main point, that the educator must avoid at all costs "education with inert ideas — that is to say, ideas that are merely received into the mind without being utilised, or tested, or thrown into fresh combinations." (p. 2) Whitehead insists that the child should be taught few but important ideas, in such a way that he can "make them his own" and utilise them. He should "experience the joy of discovery." But the worth of ideas needs to be proved, and their connection with other ideas shown. There must be specialization, but never disconnected from the one main "subject-matter for education... life in all ite manifestations." (p. 10) Utilising an idea means "relating it to that stream, compounded of sense perceptions, feelings, hopes, desires and of mental activities adjusting thought to thought, which forms our life." (p. 4)

Whitehead's tendency to idealist subjectivism emerges even more clearly on p. 18 when he says: "What education has to impart is an intimate sense for the power of ideas, for the beauty of ideas, and for the structure of ideas, together with a particular body of knowledge which has peculiar reference to the life of the being possessing it."

In a similar vein he advocates the development in students of what he calls "the most austere of all mental qualities ... the sense for style" (p. 19), that is, "an aesthetic sense, based on admiration for the direct attainment of a foreseen end, simply and without waste ...". For "style is the ultimate morality of mind." In this passage Whitehead might well be speaking of the virtue of order (in its intellectual aspect), but since nowhere in this essay does he make any reference to the intellect or to truth or to the capacity of the intellect to know things, one must conclude that despite his conviction as a natural scientist that we do know ordinary external objects (a chair, a tree, a dog, etc.), Whitehead's theory of knowledge is quite inadequate, being on the one hand empiricist — he cannot account satisfactorily for the way the intellect, through abstraction, grasps the essence of material things — and on the other hand being idealist, giving an exaggerated importance to ideas (especially in the logical order).

Again, in a later passage, Whitehead employs his own peculiar language to speak about something which seems to resemble will-power and even love. On p. 20 he says: "But above style and above knowledge, there is something, a vague shape like fate above the Greek gods. That something is Power. Style is the fashioning of power, the restraining of power. But, after all, the power of attainment of the desired end is fundamental. The first thing is to get there." However, Whitehead makes no reference to the good as the object of the will, and the reader is left perplexed both as to what ideas are useful and as to what ends students should be encouraged to desire and attain.

Whitehead appears ready to help the reader out of this perplexity when on p. 23 he says that "the essence of education is that it be religious." But by this Whitehead simply means "an education which inculcates duty and reverence," and Whitehead's conception of duty and reverence is once again both subjectivist and question-begging: "Duty arises from our potential control over the course of events. Where attainable knowledge could have changed this issue, ignorance has the guilt of vice. And the foundation of reverence is this perception, that the present holds within itself the complete sum of existence, backwards and forwards, that whole amplitude of time which is eternity." Here, like Hegel, Whitehead seems to be attempting to fuse time and eternity, as if it were possible for human created reason to attain the viewpoint of God.

Thus the several worthwhile points Whitehead makes — for instance, his insistence that "no absolutely rigid curriculum" should be imposed on schools, but rather each school, as "the true educational unit in any national system", should "be considered in relation to its special circumstances" — are weakened, if not even vitiated by his idealism and lack of clarity about the true ends of education, even on the strictly human level.

II The Rhythm of Education

This essay discusses the question: at what age should students undertake different subjects and different modes of study? Making use of Hegel's analysis of progress into Thesis, Antithesis and Synthesis, Whitehead asserts that the stages of mental growth — life being essentially periodic and even cyclical — may be roughly analysed into three: the stage of romance, the stage of precision and the stage of generalization. University education should be mainly concerned with the third stage: "The function of a University is to enable you to shed details in favour of principles." (p. 42)

In this essay, as in several of the others, Whitehead reveals his tendency not to distinguish clearly between matter and spirit due to a naturalistic orientation. For example, "the mind and the brain develop so as to adapt themselves to the many-hued world in which their lot is cast". (p. 33)

III The Rhythmic Claims of Freedom and Education

In this essay Whitehead emphasizes that the aim of education is wisdom, not knowledge. But it becomes clear that Whitehead's conception of wisdom is more aesthetic than intellectual or moral. In a key passage (pp. 62-63) he says: "The ultimate motive power, alike in science, in morality and in religion, is the sense of value, the sense of importance. It takes the various forms of wonder, of curiosity, of reverence, of worship, of tumultuous desire for merging personality in something beyond itself... The most penetrating exhibition of this force is the sense of beauty, the aesthetic sense of realized perfection." On p. 64 he says: "History shows us that an efflorescence of art is the first activity of nations on the road to civilisation."

Nowhere does Whitehead show any awareness either that the best art has always been inspired by religion (see the numerous illustrations of this point in the works of Christopher Dawson) or that art is eminently of the intellectual order (see Maritain's Art and Scholasticism).

IV Technical Education and Its Relation to Science and Literature

Whitehead criticizes the post-Renaissance Platonist tendency to split the mind from the body and emphasizes the great importance in education of linking theory to practice. He praises the early Benedictine monks "who saved for mankind the vanishing civilisation of the ancient world by linking together knowledge, labour, and moral energy." (p. 91) He emphasizes that "essentially culture should be for action, and its effect should be to divest labour from the associations of aimless toil." He criticizes the parasitism of the academic world: "The second-handedness of the learned world is the secret of its mediocrity. It is tame because it has never been scared by the facts."

However, once again, in the midst of several valid and worthwhile points, Whitehead reveals his naturalism, in this case under the form of the theory of evolution: "It is a moot point whether the human hand created the human brain, or the brain created the hand." (p. 78) And: "In the contest of the races which in its final issues will be decided in the workshops and not on the battlefield, the victory will belong to those who are masters of stores of trained nervous energy, working under conditions favourable to growth." (p. 91)

V The Place of Classics in Education

Like many of his generation Whitehead had a high appreciation for classical Greek and Roman civilisation and for its educational value as a field of study. In particular he sees the study of Latin as "the best stimulus for mental expansion" and the study of the history of Rome as the principal key to understanding European civilisation: "The history of Europe is the history of Rome curbing the Hebrew and the Greek, with their various impulses of religion, and of science, and of art, and of quest for material comfort, and of lust of domination, which are all at daggers drawn with each other. The vision of Rome is the vision of the unity of civilisation." (p. 115)

While by no means unaware of some of the limitations of Roman culture, Whitehead considers that the special merit of the study of that civilisation "in the education of youth is its concreteness, its inspiration to action, and the uniform greatness of persons, in their characters and their staging". Their aims were great, their virtues were great, and their vices were great. They had the saving merit of sinning with their cart-ropes."

Whitehead's main point is that: "Moral education is impossible apart from the habitual vision of greatness" since "the sense of greatness is the groundwork of morals." (pp. 106-107) Unfortunately, true to type, Whitehead lets himself be carried away by a somewhat superficial lyricism and proceeds to lay down the dangerously vague and tendentious maxim: "If we are not great, it does not matter what we do or what is the issue." (p. 106)

Here and elsewhere, one cannot but get the impression that Whitehead's knowledge of classical culture — and even more so of early and medieval Christian culture — is quite limited and uneven. His generalizations are consequently often superficial compared, for instance, with those of a historian such as Christopher Dawson (e.g., his essay St. Augustine and His Age.) Also, as a member of the British Empire not yet exposed to the criticisms that became commonplace in the late 1930's and 1940's, he was obviously blind to much of the dark underside of Imperial expansion and conquest. He would have benefitted from a reading of some parts of St. Augustine's City of God.

VI The Mathematical Curriculum

In this essay Whitehead again exhibits his acceptance of the theory of evolution (in its total sense), viz.: "... for the human mind was not evolved in the bygone ages for the sake of reasoning, but merely to enable mankind with more art to hunt between meals for fresh food supplies." (p. 127)

For the most part this essay is an explanation of how the mathematical curriculum should be and can be an excellent training in logical method.

VII Universities and Their Function

Whitehead sees the justification for a university in its capacity to preserve "the connection between knowledge and the zest for life, by uniting the young and the old in the imaginative consideration of learning..." (p. 139) Thus "the whole point of a university, on its educational side, is to bring the young under the intellectual influence of a band of imaginative scholars." (p. 150)

In this essay one or two of Whitehead's historical judgements seem a little exaggerated, in function of Whitehead's tendency to esteem imagination more highly than intellect. He says, for instance: "The New England Puritans of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries were the most intensely imaginative people, restrained in their outward expression, and fearful of symbolism by physical beauty, but, as it were, racked with the intensity of spiritual truths intellectually imagined." (p. 152) Such a judgement — intended as a compliment — though not without its truth, says nothing of the narrow religious fanaticism which characterized not a few Puritans of those centuries (well described by Arthur Miller in his play The Crucible).

Conclusion

Whitehead's many valid and useful observations and recommendations in these essays are unfortunately compromised, that is, undermined, by his inadequate and vague philosophy of man. In subscribing to the theory of evolution — one would guess very much in its Darwinian form — Whitehead is unable to distinguish clearly between matter and spirit, between the senses and the intellect, and thus between right and wrong. It is noteworthy that very seldom, if at all, does he make any reference to the notions of truth and goodness. In the last resort his is a materialist philosophy of man, since he fails to give any criterion for distinguishing between man and the animals. Needless to say, Whitehead has little real understanding of religion.

It is very instructive to compare this work of Whitehead's with Maritain's Education at the Crossroads (Yale, 1943) which covers much of the same ground, but at a much deeper level. Because of his training in Thomistic metaphysics Maritain is able to throw a flood of light on the potentially valid points of Whitehead, liberating them, so to speak, from the vague, superficial and ultimately materialist Weltanschauung in which they are clothed.

For a criticism of the liberal attitude to education implicit everywhere in Whitehead (especially classical education) it is also instructive to read T. S. Eliot's Modern Education and the Classics (1932) in which the relevance of the classics to the preservation of Christian values is well put over.

 

                                                                                                                  J.W. (1985)

 

Volver al Índice de las Recensiones del Opus Dei

Ver Índice de las notas bibliográficas del Opus Dei

Ir al INDEX del Opus Dei

Ir a Libros silenciados y Documentos internos (del Opus Dei)

Ir a la página principal