GULA,
Richard M.
Reason
Informed by Faith, Foundations ofCatholic Morality
Paulist
Press, 1989.
1.
General.
This
well-written and skilfully presentedbook can give the uncritical reader the
impression of an objective and reasonedstudy; one which shows how the progress
marked by major trends in current moralthinking is in an essential line of
continuity with the best of our Catholicpast (especially St. Thomas). The book,
however, does not stand up to anyrigorous analysis, especially in the light of
what is implied in its title.
The
title is quite misleading. In theauthor's analysis of Catholic morality, Faith
is not the norm, principle orguide, which "informs" Reason. It is
Experience, not Reason, that isreally offered as the governing principle for
the development of moraltheology. "Morality Informed by Experience",
would be a more accuratetitle.
While
the tone is of one who wishes topresent a fair and balanced "overview of
the present state of thediscipline" of moral theology, in practice the
morality offered issubjective, individualist, experiential and proportionalist.
The
author writes with great self-assurance,especially in claiming (or taking for
granted) that the progressive school oftheology he embraces is much more
strictly rational than what went before, orto the present alternatives (cfr.
47; 136; 154ss; 210-211; 224-225; 235-236,etc.). Yet his own
"experiential" approach is to the detriment ofrationality.
2.
Confusion of terminology.
His
book can confuse the average reader allthe more because of the way he uses
terms. He claims that his approach ispersonalist and community-based (when it
rather is individualist); is consonantwith the natural law (which he voids by
holding human nature to be in constantevolution); is not relativistic or
subjectivistic Ñ see, e.g. pp. 293-294 Ñ(when, throughout, he denies any
universally valid norms, and leaves each onebasically on his or her own in
coming to moral judgments). For his ultimatesubjectivism, see also 305-306.
3.
The "rationality" ofautonomous ethics.
He
presentes "autonomous ethics"(with main exponents being Joseph Fuchs,
Bruno Schuller, Charles Curran,Richard McCormick), as a reaction against making
moral theology excessivelydependent on faith, and a movement towards grounding
it more on natural law.This runs througout the book. The "new"
morality is not only more"personalistic" and
"experiential", but also more based onreason; and therefore in the
true tradition of e.g. St. Thomas Aquinas. Theimpression is created that the
autonomous ethics theologians base theirpositions on deeply reasoned arguments
(which is precisely what one so oftenfinds lacking in them), whereas the
traditionalists Ñ as also represented inmost magisterial documents Ñ simply
appeal to faith, and not to reason, tojustify an outdated position. This he
dismisses as the "faith-ethics"position, represented in particular by
Joseph Ratzinger and Philip Delhaye(48).
He
repeatedly gives the impression that themajor positions he sustains find
support in St. Thomas Aquinas (on Natural LawÑ 223ss; on rationalism v.
voluntarism Ñ pp. 256ss; on the difference betweenformal and material norms Ñ
292ss; on proportionalism (a "form ofteleology": 303), where he
presents Fuchs, Janssens, R. McCormick andBruno Schuller as users, like Thomas,
of the teleological method, in oppositionto the deontoligical method
(301-302ss).
The
pre-conciliar approach to law in theChurch was voluntaristic; we have now
passed over to a more rationalisticapproach, more in keeping with the true
spirit of justice as presented by St.Thomas (Ch. 17).
In
the chapter "Natural LawToday", he seeks to apply the distinction
"order of nature"/"order of reason" to magisterial
documents. Casti connubii, HumanaeVitae, the Declaration on Certain Questions
concerning Sexual Ethics, are allexamples of the approach "making the
order of nature superior to the orderof reason in sexual matters" (232).
All
of this can blind the unthinking readerto the fact that it is reason itself
which teaches what is the right and wronguse of the sexual faculty. His
accusation is that the traditional physicalistview allowed biological
structures, and not true personalist values, todetermine sexual morality
(231ss; cf. 63-64). Though he claims to identify hispersonalism with the order
of reason, his position makes any rational analysisof human sexuality Ñ body
and spirit Ñ impossible.
4.
"Experiential wisdom".
Reason,
for him, "includes observationand research, intuition, affection, common
sense, and an aestheticsense..." (224). Note, for instance, his phrase:
"We are notsubjected in a fated way to the inner finality of nature. We
discover whatnatural law requires by reason reflecting on what is given in
human experienceto lead to authentic human life..." (228). Her the three
words,"natural law", "requires" and "reason",
have clearlyall been emptied of significance, the operative word
being"experience". So one understands the basic principle he has
laiddown: "The proximate norm of morality is authentic human
existence"(224). Cf. p. 235: "The work of reason is to discover moral
value in theexperience of the reality of being human". On p.239, he
presents the"Source of Moral norms", within the order of reason, as
"HumanExperience"... (cf. p. 73; McCormick, p.275). "moral norms
arederived from the experience of value"; "they express
experientialwisdom" (284).
So
it is not in reason or in Revelation,but basically in "experience"
(which at times he qualifies as"community experience"), that moral
norms find their rationale andsource. "Because moral norms take seriously
the repetitive aspects ofhuman experience, they provide a reliable point of
reference and direction formoral living" (284). Yet, in the end, the view
he offers of such norms iswholly subjectivist (e.g. 285).
He
speaks on p. 295 of the dangers of a"creeping legalism", in the
traditional concept of moral absolutes.He seems oblivious of the "creeping
subjectivism" of the approach heproposes which makes it useless as a guide
to moral thinking, formation,orcounselling. In fact the thrust of the approach
of the book (by a Seminaryprofessor) is that the pastoral function of the
moralist is "not so muchproviding answers to moral questions as
encouraging the process of arriving ata moral decision" (136).
He
claims to show that the Encyclicals,etc. on the Church's social teaching are
examples of ethical teaching whichuses the "order of reason approach to
natural law"; and so they showgreater flexibility and have greater respect
for "experience", incontrast to physicalist teaching on sexual
ethics.
He
insists that in the Church's ongoing"learning-teaching process", with
its necessary expressions ofdissent, "the point of reference... must be
the world" (207).
While
accepting that God's Will must be"mediated" for us, he says that only
"our personal religiousexperience of God...can test the authenticity of
the mediation" (262).
5.
A "Personalist" analysis Ñconditioned by history.
"The
human person is the mostappropriate point of departure for elaborating on the
meaning of morality ingeneral and... for dealing with specific moral
questions" (63). But hisrelativism, his ignoring of Revelation, and his
practical rejection of NaturalLaw (see below) make it impossible for him to
clarify his "point ofdeparture": i.e. who or what is the human
person. He says "inpersonalist morality the human person adequately
considered is the criterionfor discovering whether an act is morally
right" (64). But the analysisoffered of the human person "adequately
considered" (66ss), isterribly inadequate. 1 Following Janssens, he gives
these fundamentaldimensions: man is a "relational being", an
"embodiedsubject", one "fundamentally equal to others but
uniquelyoriginal" and an "historical being"(67). The application
of thecriterion means that an action is morally right if it is beneficial to
theperson considered adequately Ñ in the first three dimensions. "ForJanssens
this is an objective criterion since it is based on the constantdimensions of
being human". But he then blandly adds: "But since itis a criterion about
the human person as an historical being,it requires aregular review of the
possibilities we have available to promote the humanperson so that we can
determine whether they truly do so. Janssens recognizesthat the application of
this criterion is not easy" (73). (Good forJanssens!). As is obvious,
"historicity" dominates the moralcriterion and pulverizes its
"objectivity".
The
"new" view of theologyrejects unchanging principles and essences, and
accepts that constantlychanging historical situations make truth and certainty
very relative things: cf.pp. 30ss. He praises magisterial documents in which he
sees "historicalconsciousness" (noticeable in the field of social
teaching) and criticizesthose that lack it (noticeable above all in the field
of sexual ethics)
6.
Values, feeling, imagination and heart.
Moral
knowledge is not"conceptual"; it is "evaluative knowledge",
"feltknowledge", that comes from the heart (85). It is "the
self-involvingknowledge which makes deciding and acting on behalf of what we
value truly ourown. Without this knowledge we act merely by hearsay, by what we
are told isright, rather than on the basis of what we have discovered to
bevaluable"(87). cf. p. 109: "Only then ["when we have
reachedevaluative knowledge"] is mortal sin possible".
"Only
a small part of the moral lifeis influenced by the specific, conscious
instruction which the church provideson moral issues. A considerably large part
is influenced by the church's effecton the imagination". So, he concludes,
the task of pastoral ministry Ñ inteaching, etc. Ñ is "to retell and
reenact] the stories of faith in orderto fashion a Christian imagination"
... "By allowing our imaginationsto be transformed by these stories, we
discover the truly redemptive responsesto life" (200). On p. 296ss, he
returns to the importance of "theimaginative process to deepen the meaning
of accepted (moral) norms and to testthe adequacy of their formulations". Cf.
also pp. 71-72.
He
attaches special importance to theliturgy for this task; but thinks the liturgical
reform has so far failed. Amain reason is its present "excessive reliance
on verbal forms ofcommunicating the mystery of divine love". Non-verbal
artistic forms Ñdance, drama, etc. Ñ "can make a strong appeal to the
moralimagination". A second reason is its "sex-exclusive"
malelanguage and structure (201).
See
below, no. 15, on the "imaginativeshock" of Jesus' "Radical
sayings".
7.
Natural Law.
From
Chs. 15 through 19, he relativises andin effect destroys the concept of the
natural law. However, having rejected thereality, he then continues to use the
term, so as to give apparent rationalauthority to his support of dissent on
specific points, his criticism ofobedience, etc.
"The
natural law is central to Romancatholic moral theology". The advantage of
using it is that Church canpresent its teachings to all men, independently of
belief; but in this he seesa corresponding disadvantage because it leads
"to handing Christianmorality over to moral philosophy wherein religious
beliefs do not really makea difference for moral claims" (220).
He
draws a contrast between the order ofnature, "focused on the physical and
biological structures given in natureas the source of morality", and the
order of reason, "focused on thehuman capacity to discover in experience
what befits human well-being".Affirming that "St. Thomas accepted
both", he claims that vacillationÑ as to which of the two offers the right
foundation for moral teaching Ñ"has caused great confusion in Catholic
moral thought" (223-224).
In
effect he says that traditional Catholicmorality has, especially in sexual
matters, put the order of nature("physicalism") over the order of
reason (which, according to hispresentation, might also be called
"Personalism": 226, par 2; end of232-223). Physicalism looks on
nature "as a finished product prescribingGod's moral will and commanding a
fixed moral response" (228). "Themodern worldview of contemporary
morality" rejects this; "rather, itlooks on nature as evolving"
(ib). At the same time as he thus destroysany objective notion of the natural
law, he also destroys the instrument Ñreason Ñ by which we can know it. This, I
think, is the really dangerous threadthat runs especially through his
presentation: claiming to have "reason"on his side, while in fact his
reference point is not reason at all, but"experience";
"evolution", etc.
Logically,
since human nature is inevolution, any "specific moral conclusions based
on natural law... mustnecessarily be open to revision since more of the meaning
of being human is yetto be discovered" (235-236). "Since
"nature" is constantlychanging... change, revision, and development
would be constitutive of thenatural moral law" (240). He insists that this
is the view of"contemporary theology", which in consequence
recognizes "theprovisional character of moral knowledge". At this
stage it is perfectlyclear that the term "natural law", as he uses
it, is emptied of anyreal content.
After
two chapters in which he apparentlyaccepts "nature" and "natural
law" (conditioned, however,by their changing and evolutionary character)
his basic hostility to theconcept of "nature" appears quite clearly
on p. 245. He describes"Gaudium et Spes" as "a landmark document
for the shift from"nature" to "person" in an official
Churchdocument"... It is an elementary philosophical error to oppose, as
hedoes, "nature" and "person"; and to think that to focus
onone, is necessarily to deemphasizethe other.2 He calmly adds the
"nonsequitur" that the "shift" from nature to person"acknowledges
... what all persons have incommon"...
8.
Freedom.
While
he speaks o the dangers ofdeterminism, he would seem to over-stress the
limitations on our freedom which"the behavioral sciences have clearly
shown". Freedom means "toexpress oneself within one's own limits and
according to one's ownpredispositions" (76). "The more we are able to
become aware ofourselves and possess ourselves, including all the determining
influences, themore we will experience ourselves as responsible for what we do
and who webecome" (77).
We
need "commitment to our ownintegrity and identity... resist[ing] those
strong determining forces which areconstantly... fighting to make us someone
else" (81). I show more freedomin doing what I want, than in doing what I
ought... (82).
9.
The Church and the Magisterium.
While
he lists "church" (writtenthroughout in low case) among the sources
of moral guidance, the Chapter on the"Church and moral Life" presents
a protestant image of the Church:Jesus present in the believing and acting
community (199ss).
He
speaks of the church as the "bearerof moral tradition": bearer,
rather than teacher... (202).
He
acknowledges that the Magisterium is a"source of moral authority". However,
omitting an exposition of thescriptural and ecclesiological ground for the
special charism of theMagisterium,3
he immediately makesthe validity of magisterial teaching depend on the
proper observation ofconsultative processes (154).
He
considers "the teaching aspects ofthree different groups within the
church: the faithful, theologians andpastoral ministers, and the
hierarchy" He makes an elementary confusionbetween catechesis and
Magisterium in insisting that "the real teachers inthe church are not the
bishops but first the family and then thecatechists" (202).
Theologians:
he assigns them the role ofinterpreters of the "givens of the apostolic
faith", including"the ongoing formulations of the magisterium". He
insists thetheologians, with their "somewhat independent role", must
be allowedto carry on their critical function, "to test the given
teaching...against scripture and tradition as well as to use critically the
human sciencesin order to keep the teaching sound and applicable to
contemporary living"(204).
Pastoral
ministers: "bring theteaching... into contact with the specific lives of
the people". They"must communicate the substance of scripture and
teaching of the churchrealistically", being aware "also of what the
particular context ofthe people is demanding" (204-5: emphasis added).
Hierarchy:
Having assigned to thetheologians the mission of keeping the apostolic teaching
sound, and ofinterpreting it,he says the responsibility of the hierarchy is to
"affirm,protect and promote" this testimony of the apostles. He
assigns to theHierarchy alone the task of designating "certain
interpretations of theapostolic faith as the official interpretations of the
Catholic Church whichare to guide pastoral practice. We speak of this as the
function of the ÇauthoritativemagisteriumÈ(205). Not only is there no mention
whatever of the scriptural andecclesiological basis to the function and charism
of the Magisterium, but theimpression has already been left that it is the
function of thetheologians to provide interpretations, other than those that
are strictly"authoritative", so as "to keep the teaching
sound"...
Whenever
speaking of "dissent","pluralism", etc. he always allows
that authority must exist and beexercised, so as to avoid chaos (cf. 205; 216);
but his presentation comes downclearly on the side of individual conscience.
10.
Dissent.
Of
the 18 pages making up the chapter,"The Church and the Moral Life",
more than 12 are devoted to"The Church as a Community of Moral
Deliberation" (206-217; and of these,8 pages to "Dissent", with
a strong apologia for "loyal"and "responsible" dissent (207ss).
He
inaccurately equates the conditionalassent, permitted by the manuals, with
dissent (208).
211:
He invokes the tradition ofprobabilism to sustain his argument that a
dissenting position can beresponsible if "supported by a considerable
number of ÇexpertsÈ in thefield...However, determining who are the true experts
in the field can be difficultto do, especially for the non-specialist". This
precisely ignores thepoint that the Magisterium is the only ÇspecialistÈ with
the charism todetermine who is a true expert. It of course also ignores that
probabilism hasits application as between views that the Church accepts or has
not condemned.
On
the same page, he passes over the thirdcriterion for responsible dissent laid
down by the US Catholic Bishops in1968,which he had mentioned on p. 208:
"the dissent must be such as not togive scandal".
"The
aim of dissent is to try toconvince the magisterium that a present formulation
of a teaching is inadequateor erroneous ... dissent can be a service to the
church when it recognizes thatteaching is incomplete and inaccurate as it
stands". The aim of responsibledissent is that "the formulation of
the substance of the teaching [belrevised..." If this is not done, and the
church, as a result, continues"promoting a truly defective teaching",
this can lead "topossible disillusionment for people that the church is a
reliable teacher"(214:emphasis added).
Dissent
has a responsibility "toprotect the overall good of the church and the
credibility of themagisterium" (213); as an example of the negative
results that follow ifthis responsibility is not fulfilled, he instances how
"the church'scredibility on matters of sexuality is already severely
damaged" (thereason for this apparently being a lack of adequate dissent...).
The
seriousness with which the"responsible" dissenter sees his mission
emerges well in these pages.The trouble is that the criterion for knowing when
some aspect of acceptedteaching is "inaccurate",
"defective" or"erroneous", and in urgent need of
"substantial" revisionapparently lies in the hands of the dissenter
himself. So, in effect, thedissenter's being a responsible and autonomous
critic of the magisterium is amatter of self-designation.
Earlier
he had cited "HumanaeVitae" as an example of non-infallible teaching
in moral matters, going onto say that conscience nevertheless cannot simply
ignore it. Yet his conclusionis that, in such cases, the
"presumption" in favour of theMagisterium must yield to clear
contrary evidence, which would also include"the person's subjective
capacity... to measure up to the specificbehavior prescribed by the
teaching" (160).
11.
Conscience.
He
suggests that the Magisterium itselfcountenances two different criteria for
relating law and morality: according toone, it is the natural law which is the
norm for positive law; according to theother (based on par. 7 of Dignitatis
Humanae), it is personal conscience(253-255).
He
suggests that "rules" areopposed to freedom of conscience; and that
accepting authority is a sign of animmature conscience (123-124).
Following
John Glaser, he thinks that theCatholic who is sensitive to tradition, to
authority, who confesses frequently,shows a warped conscience Ñ a
"Superego" (124ss.).
He follows T. O'Connell,
"Principlefor a Catholic Morality", in the distinction of
Conscience/1/2/3...Conscience/3 (which O'C. holds is infallible), "is the
only sure guide foraction by a free and knowing person. Violating Concience/3
would be violatingour integrity" (135).
He explicitly defends the right of
aCatholic couple, in certain circumstances, to use artificial birth
control(160).
12. Moral Norms.
His distinction of
"formal" and"material" moral norms closely follows that of
T. O'Connell (e.g."Principles for a Catholic Morality", pp. 159ss.).
Formal norms(O'Connell' "being-values" which are the only true moral
value) arethe only absolute norms; they exist however only as
"fundamentalvalues" [whose "specific expressions... inevitably
belong toparticular cultures and historical epochs" (287). Material
norms("doing-values" or premoral values) "relate to the sort
ofactions we ought to perform". Not being absolute, they are governed by
theprinciple of proportionalism. A (negative) material norm as, for
instance,"the proscription of contraception", ought" to be
interpreted ascontaining the implied qualifier... 'unless there is a
proportionatereason'..." (290-291).
"The lack of proportionate
reason isprecisely what makes acting contrary to a specific material norm...
morallywrong"(292). From this it follows that if the proportionate reason
exists,then it is not wrong to e.g. commit adultery, practice contraception
orabortion, to lie..., etc. He approvingly quotes Edward Vacek (as speaking
for,i.a., Josef Fuchs, Louis Janssens, Richard McCormick) that "one can
neverbe theoretically certain that a given act is always wrong" (293). So,
onecan never be sure that, not only adultery, but, say, bestiality, is always
andin all circumstances wrong... In fact, at the start of the chapter (283),
hehad allowed that absolute norms do exist, but had warned against the danger
ofmaking all moral norms absolute.The danger seems to have been quite avoided.
He incorrectly states that if one
acceptsthe principle of intrinsic or absolute evil, which "according to
officialRoman Catholic teaching" applies to many actions, it becomes
"thesole criterion for judging the morality of an action" (302)
Affirming that Jesus does not
"providea moral system as such", he implies that his only specific
moral commandis love (285-286).
13. Sin and Fundamental Option.
Sin is "the failure to be
fullyresponsible" (90). The concept of social sin predominates.4 I do not find the sins of pride, lust,or
gluttony, mentioned.
He defines original sin as
"the humancondition of living in a world where we are influenced by more evil
than thatwhich we do ourselves" (100; 106). It "makes actual and
social sinpossible" (107).
A sin is mortal when
"deliberatelycommitted with the intention of making a personal affront to
God" (114).
In his presentation on pp.
109-110, the'serious matter' required as one of the conditions for mortal sin,
loses allpractical importance beside the other two conditions: full consent
andsufficient reflection.
In his fundamental option
presentation ofmortal sin, an individual act of adultery (which is the example
he gives) isnot really mortal unless it reflects a general direction of
infidelity inmarried life (111-112). Pastors, etc. formed in the principles he
enunciateshere would always answer "It depends",if asked by a
personcontemplating adultery, abortion, or homosexual conduct, whether this
would bea mortal sin or not (cf. 112-113).
14. Proportionalism.
He follows J. Fuchs in rejecting
the notionof "intrinsic evil", as ignoring the proper analysis of
actions intotheir "pre-moral" elements: from which, he says,derives
"theinevitable ambiguity of human actions" which "mean that all
humanactions contain some features which enhance our humanity and some
featureswhich restrict it" (268-269).
Criticising the Principle of
Double Effect(in common with Fuchs, etc.), he rejects the idea of actions that
can be"good in themselves"; he goes on to say: "we...
inevitably...commit some premoral/ontic evil to achieve good" (271), where
what hepresumably should be saying is that, in doing good, we may commit or
cause some(apparent or real) physical evil.
With the rest of the
proportionalists, heconcludes Ñthough he avoids putting it into such wordsÑ
that the end justifiesthe means, or that evil can be done so that good may be
achieved. Once theprinciple is admitted, it becomes impossible to maintain any
convincing moralstand not only against e.g. contraception, abortion or
voluntary euthanasia,but also against compulsory euthanasia, eugenic
infanticide, laws penalizingcertain religious bodies because of their tenets
(religious discrimination),racial discrimination, etc. His argument against a
"utilitarianinterpretation of proportionality" is quite arbitrary,
with no rationalsupport (272-273).
Applications of proportionalism:
adulteryis considered "disproportionate" as a means of protecting the
valueof sexuality (275).
His criterion for avoiding the
danger ofsubjectivism inherent in proportionalism is reliance "on
communaldiscernment... drawing upon the wisdom of past experience as it is
embodied inthe community's standards" (278).
He speaks of proportionalism as a
means"for determining the objective morality of human actions"
(283),whereas, since the criteria on which the theory ultimately rests are
allrelative, it is, at most, a means for determining the subjective morality
ofactions. It offers no criterion for an objective moral judgment.
He does not really rebut the
objection that"Proportionalism does not allow for specific universal
norms"(278-279).
15. Residual Points noted.
Ñ Ch. 12 "Scripture in MoralTheology":
Apart from the all-important
commandment to"love", Scripture really lays down no God-given moral
norms for ourconduct. The Ten Commandments are mentioned as an expression of
God's Covenant,inviting our response; but the Commandments establish presumptions,
rather thanrules (172-173).
The parable of Jesus stir our
hearts, whilehis "Radical sayings" have the value of causing an
"imaginativeshock" (therefore, he describes the saying about a
lustful look beingequivalent to adultery committed in the heart, as a
"hyperbolicmetaphor" (179).
Recourse to the Bible in the moral
life ispossible, but "very difficult". But it remains necessary as
"theprimary source for the stories and images which fashion a
Christianimagination..." (181).
Ñ Ch. 13 "Jesus andDiscipleship":
Perhaps the only significant thing
here isthe brevity of the treatment of the Cross in the moral life: just a few
lines,where its significance lies in how it "reveals the emptiness of
alloppressive power" (196). Nowhere in the book, as far as I have noticed,
isthe idea of self-denial Ñ as a key to Christian moral growth Ñ presented.
Ñ Chapter 17: "Law
andObedience":
Criticism of any practice of
making positivelaws binding under sin, or of taking guidelines or ideals for
moral behaviour,and "reducing" them to laws. Without the exercise of
discernment,obedience is mere legalism which is oppressive and devoid of real
virtue(262-263).
Ñ
For him morality cannot mean"fitting into the divine plan"; if it
did, "then human freedomand responsibility would not really matter in the
moral life". Rather"God's will gives a general orientation for our
lives, but the specificsare left to us... the will of God is not so fixed from
the beginning that itexcludes human involvement" (318-319). The essence,
dignity and greatnessof the ideal of Christian moral living Ñ the free response
of each one of us toa personal vocation coming from God, and a particular will
of God for each oneÑ seem to escape him totally here.
C.B.(1990)
Volver al êndice de
las Recensiones del Opus Dei
Ver êndice de
las notas bibliogr‡ficas del Opus Dei
Ir a
Libros silenciados y Documentos internos (del Opus Dei)